Anil Seth on Consciousness as a Controlled Hallucination
Neuroscientist Anil Seth explains how our sense of self and reality are not direct perceptions, but the brain's predictions rooted in our biology.
Neuroscientist Anil Seth explains how our sense of self and reality are not direct perceptions, but the brain's predictions rooted in our biology.
Anil Seth, a neuroscientist and professor, is a leading voice in the study of consciousness. His work investigates the biological foundations of this complex phenomenon, a significant challenge in science. This article will explore Anil Seth’s core theories, examining how he conceptualizes consciousness, the scientific methods he employs, and the broader implications of his research.
Anil Seth’s central argument is that our experience of the world is not a direct window onto an objective reality. Instead, he proposes that what we perceive is a form of “controlled hallucination” generated by the brain. This idea rests on the framework of predictive processing, which reframes the nature of perception from a passive reception of information to an active, constructive process. The brain, according to this model, is constantly generating hypotheses or predictions about the causes of incoming sensory signals.
Sensory data—the light hitting our retinas, the sound waves reaching our ears—acts as a continuous stream of feedback. This feedback serves to update and correct the brain’s predictions. The difference between the brain’s prediction and the actual sensory input is known as “prediction error.” The goal of the perceptual system is to minimize this error over time.
The process is “controlled” because it is constantly being reined in and anchored by the sensory information flowing from the world. Optical illusions provide a compelling example of this; in many illusions, the brain fills in missing information or makes an incorrect guess about the cause of a sensory pattern, revealing the constructive nature of perception. This model explains why our expectations can powerfully shape what we perceive. When you are expecting a certain word in a noisy conversation, you are more likely to “hear” it, even if the acoustic signal is ambiguous. The brain’s prior belief or prediction influences the final perception.
Seth extends his framework from the external world to our internal universe, proposing that our very sense of self is also a product of the brain’s predictive machinery. He introduces the concept of the “beast machine,” which posits that consciousness is deeply intertwined with our biological nature as living organisms. This idea emphasizes that the fundamental drive to stay alive is not separate from our conscious experience but is, in fact, its foundation. Our minds are not disembodied computers; they are embodied and exist to manage our physiology.
Central to this concept is the process of interoception. Interoception is the nervous system’s ability to sense and regulate the internal state of the body. It involves monitoring a constant stream of signals related to heart rate, blood pressure, core temperature, inflammation, and other physiological variables. These signals are what give rise to fundamental feelings like hunger, thirst, pain, and pleasure, as well as the spectrum of our emotional lives.
According to Seth, the experience of being a self emerges from the brain’s continuous effort to predict and control these internal bodily states. Emotions, in this view, can be understood as a form of controlled hallucination about the internal state of the body, shaped by the imperative of physiological regulation.
This perspective grounds the self firmly in the body’s biology. The fundamental feeling of being alive is a perception of the body’s successful regulation. This distinguishes the perception of the self from the outside world by tying it to internal signals that confirm our status as a living creature. The self is not a static entity but an ongoing process of embodied perception.
Seth’s theories are not just philosophical propositions but frameworks that guide empirical research. He and his team at the Sackler Centre for Consciousness Science investigate these ideas using various methods to make subjective experience scientifically tractable, breaking down consciousness into specific, measurable components.
One way his lab categorizes consciousness is by distinguishing between its levels, contents, and self. The level of consciousness refers to the difference between being awake and alert versus being in a dreamless sleep or under anesthesia. These states can be characterized by measuring the complexity and diversity of neural activity using techniques like electroencephalography (EEG).
The contents of consciousness refer to the specific qualities of any given experience—the redness of a sunset, the sound of a particular voice, or a feeling of happiness. Researchers can study these specific experiences using neuroimaging tools like functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) and computational modeling. For instance, by presenting participants with specific stimuli in controlled experiments, scientists can observe which patterns of brain activity correspond to particular conscious perceptions, testing the predictions of the predictive processing model.
Seth’s research also utilizes behavioral experiments, often employing virtual reality (VR) to manipulate a person’s sense of their body and the environment. These studies can induce illusions of body ownership or alter perceptual experiences to probe how the brain constructs its model of the self and the world. By studying how the brain responds to these manipulations, researchers can gain insight into the underlying predictive mechanisms.
The implications of Anil Seth’s work extend beyond the laboratory, offering new ways to think about mental health, technology, and our own daily lives. By framing perception and selfhood as forms of controlled hallucination, his theories provide a different lens through which to understand various psychiatric and neurological conditions.
For example, conditions like anxiety or depression could be reinterpreted as arising from dysfunctional interoceptive predictions, where the brain’s “best guess” about the body’s internal state is persistently negative or inaccurate. This perspective could also apply to psychosis, which might be understood as a state where predictive models of the world lose their grounding in sensory reality, leading to uncontrolled hallucinations. Similarly, experiences like depersonalization, where one feels detached from oneself, could be linked to disruptions in the predictive machinery that generates the sense of self. These frameworks open up new avenues for research and potential therapeutic interventions focused on retraining these predictive processes.
In the domain of artificial intelligence, Seth’s emphasis on the “beast machine” offers a counterpoint to purely computational views of consciousness. If consciousness is fundamentally tied to the biological imperative of self-preservation and the complex feedback loops of a living body, then creating a genuinely conscious AI would require more than just powerful processing. It suggests that a conscious machine would need something akin to a body with a drive to maintain its own existence, a concept far removed from current AI models.
Ultimately, understanding our brains as prediction machines can change how we view our own experiences. Seth’s work contributes to demystifying consciousness by grounding it in testable biological mechanisms, transforming it from an intractable mystery into a solvable scientific problem.